How to classify $mathbb N^2$-orbits?












6














I'm sure the answer to this question is well-known, but I don't know how to search for it. Neither do I know how to tag the question. Feel free to retag it! Or to mark it as a duplicate!



Say that an $mathbb N$-set is a set $X$ together with an endomap $s:Xto X$. The notion of isomorphism of $mathbb N$-sets is the obvious one. Given a point $x$ of an $mathbb N$-set $X$, say that the orbit of $x$ is
$$
{s^n(x) | ninmathbb N}.
$$

This is a sub-$mathbb N$-set of $X$. Say that the orbits of $xin X$ and of $yin Y$ are isomorphic if there is an isomorphism from the first to the second mapping $x$ to $y$.



The $mathbb N$-orbits are easily classified up to isomorphism, and there is an obvious analog of the above definitions with $mathbb N^2$ instead of $mathbb N$.



My question is




How to classify $mathbb N^2$-orbits?




Edit An $mathbb N^2$-set is a set equipped with two commuting endomaps.



Here is the classification of $mathbb N$-orbits up to isomorphism I'd like to generalize to $mathbb N^2$-orbits:



I'll give examples of $mathbb N$-orbits, and claim that any $mathbb N$-orbit is isomorphic to exactly one of the examples.



The first example is $mathbb N$ itself viewed as the orbit of $0$ under the standard successor map $nmapsto n+1$.



The other examples are finite, and come as a two parameter family.



Set $X:={x_0,dots,x_n}$ with $nge0$, let $k$ be an integer such that $0le kle n$, and define $s:Xto X$ by $s(x_0)=x_1,dots,s(x_{n-1})=x_n,s(x_n)=x_k$. (Such an orbit resembles the letter P - or the letter O if $k=0$.)



Let $Y$ be an orbit starting with $yin Y$.



If $Y$ is infinite, $(Y,y)$ is isomorphic to $(mathbb N,0)$ with the usual successor map.



If $Y$ is finite, there is a unique $(k,n)inmathbb N^2$ such that $(Y,y)$ is isomorphic to the orbit $(X,x_0)$ described above.



The verification is left to the reader.










share|cite|improve this question
























  • What is the "obvious analog"? I can think of a few different ways to define $mathbb{N}^2$-sets.
    – Ben W
    Dec 31 '18 at 16:26










  • Before worrying about $Bbb N^2$-orbits, what would $Bbb N^2$-sets be?
    – Arthur
    Dec 31 '18 at 16:33










  • Would it be correct to say the following? Namely, that an $mathbb N^2$-set is an action of $mathbb N^2$ on a set $X$, meaning a function $mathbb N^2 times X mapsto X$ that associates to each $vec m = (m_1,m_2) in mathbb N^2$ and each $x in X$ an element $vec m cdot x in X$, such that $(vec m + vec n) cdot x = vec m cdot ( vec n cdot x)$.
    – Lee Mosher
    Dec 31 '18 at 16:38






  • 3




    I agree with Lee. I thought that an $M$-set ($M$ a monoid) is a set $X$ equipped with a monoid morphism $Mtotext{End}(X)$. An $mathbb N^2$-set is also given by two commuting endomaps. @BenW
    – Pierre-Yves Gaillard
    Dec 31 '18 at 16:41






  • 4




    @BenW - Yes, $text{End}(X)$ is just mean the set of all maps from $X$ into itself. It's implicit that we're in the category of sets. The analog is that an $mathbb N^2$-set is given by two commuting endomaps.
    – Pierre-Yves Gaillard
    Dec 31 '18 at 18:00
















6














I'm sure the answer to this question is well-known, but I don't know how to search for it. Neither do I know how to tag the question. Feel free to retag it! Or to mark it as a duplicate!



Say that an $mathbb N$-set is a set $X$ together with an endomap $s:Xto X$. The notion of isomorphism of $mathbb N$-sets is the obvious one. Given a point $x$ of an $mathbb N$-set $X$, say that the orbit of $x$ is
$$
{s^n(x) | ninmathbb N}.
$$

This is a sub-$mathbb N$-set of $X$. Say that the orbits of $xin X$ and of $yin Y$ are isomorphic if there is an isomorphism from the first to the second mapping $x$ to $y$.



The $mathbb N$-orbits are easily classified up to isomorphism, and there is an obvious analog of the above definitions with $mathbb N^2$ instead of $mathbb N$.



My question is




How to classify $mathbb N^2$-orbits?




Edit An $mathbb N^2$-set is a set equipped with two commuting endomaps.



Here is the classification of $mathbb N$-orbits up to isomorphism I'd like to generalize to $mathbb N^2$-orbits:



I'll give examples of $mathbb N$-orbits, and claim that any $mathbb N$-orbit is isomorphic to exactly one of the examples.



The first example is $mathbb N$ itself viewed as the orbit of $0$ under the standard successor map $nmapsto n+1$.



The other examples are finite, and come as a two parameter family.



Set $X:={x_0,dots,x_n}$ with $nge0$, let $k$ be an integer such that $0le kle n$, and define $s:Xto X$ by $s(x_0)=x_1,dots,s(x_{n-1})=x_n,s(x_n)=x_k$. (Such an orbit resembles the letter P - or the letter O if $k=0$.)



Let $Y$ be an orbit starting with $yin Y$.



If $Y$ is infinite, $(Y,y)$ is isomorphic to $(mathbb N,0)$ with the usual successor map.



If $Y$ is finite, there is a unique $(k,n)inmathbb N^2$ such that $(Y,y)$ is isomorphic to the orbit $(X,x_0)$ described above.



The verification is left to the reader.










share|cite|improve this question
























  • What is the "obvious analog"? I can think of a few different ways to define $mathbb{N}^2$-sets.
    – Ben W
    Dec 31 '18 at 16:26










  • Before worrying about $Bbb N^2$-orbits, what would $Bbb N^2$-sets be?
    – Arthur
    Dec 31 '18 at 16:33










  • Would it be correct to say the following? Namely, that an $mathbb N^2$-set is an action of $mathbb N^2$ on a set $X$, meaning a function $mathbb N^2 times X mapsto X$ that associates to each $vec m = (m_1,m_2) in mathbb N^2$ and each $x in X$ an element $vec m cdot x in X$, such that $(vec m + vec n) cdot x = vec m cdot ( vec n cdot x)$.
    – Lee Mosher
    Dec 31 '18 at 16:38






  • 3




    I agree with Lee. I thought that an $M$-set ($M$ a monoid) is a set $X$ equipped with a monoid morphism $Mtotext{End}(X)$. An $mathbb N^2$-set is also given by two commuting endomaps. @BenW
    – Pierre-Yves Gaillard
    Dec 31 '18 at 16:41






  • 4




    @BenW - Yes, $text{End}(X)$ is just mean the set of all maps from $X$ into itself. It's implicit that we're in the category of sets. The analog is that an $mathbb N^2$-set is given by two commuting endomaps.
    – Pierre-Yves Gaillard
    Dec 31 '18 at 18:00














6












6








6


2





I'm sure the answer to this question is well-known, but I don't know how to search for it. Neither do I know how to tag the question. Feel free to retag it! Or to mark it as a duplicate!



Say that an $mathbb N$-set is a set $X$ together with an endomap $s:Xto X$. The notion of isomorphism of $mathbb N$-sets is the obvious one. Given a point $x$ of an $mathbb N$-set $X$, say that the orbit of $x$ is
$$
{s^n(x) | ninmathbb N}.
$$

This is a sub-$mathbb N$-set of $X$. Say that the orbits of $xin X$ and of $yin Y$ are isomorphic if there is an isomorphism from the first to the second mapping $x$ to $y$.



The $mathbb N$-orbits are easily classified up to isomorphism, and there is an obvious analog of the above definitions with $mathbb N^2$ instead of $mathbb N$.



My question is




How to classify $mathbb N^2$-orbits?




Edit An $mathbb N^2$-set is a set equipped with two commuting endomaps.



Here is the classification of $mathbb N$-orbits up to isomorphism I'd like to generalize to $mathbb N^2$-orbits:



I'll give examples of $mathbb N$-orbits, and claim that any $mathbb N$-orbit is isomorphic to exactly one of the examples.



The first example is $mathbb N$ itself viewed as the orbit of $0$ under the standard successor map $nmapsto n+1$.



The other examples are finite, and come as a two parameter family.



Set $X:={x_0,dots,x_n}$ with $nge0$, let $k$ be an integer such that $0le kle n$, and define $s:Xto X$ by $s(x_0)=x_1,dots,s(x_{n-1})=x_n,s(x_n)=x_k$. (Such an orbit resembles the letter P - or the letter O if $k=0$.)



Let $Y$ be an orbit starting with $yin Y$.



If $Y$ is infinite, $(Y,y)$ is isomorphic to $(mathbb N,0)$ with the usual successor map.



If $Y$ is finite, there is a unique $(k,n)inmathbb N^2$ such that $(Y,y)$ is isomorphic to the orbit $(X,x_0)$ described above.



The verification is left to the reader.










share|cite|improve this question















I'm sure the answer to this question is well-known, but I don't know how to search for it. Neither do I know how to tag the question. Feel free to retag it! Or to mark it as a duplicate!



Say that an $mathbb N$-set is a set $X$ together with an endomap $s:Xto X$. The notion of isomorphism of $mathbb N$-sets is the obvious one. Given a point $x$ of an $mathbb N$-set $X$, say that the orbit of $x$ is
$$
{s^n(x) | ninmathbb N}.
$$

This is a sub-$mathbb N$-set of $X$. Say that the orbits of $xin X$ and of $yin Y$ are isomorphic if there is an isomorphism from the first to the second mapping $x$ to $y$.



The $mathbb N$-orbits are easily classified up to isomorphism, and there is an obvious analog of the above definitions with $mathbb N^2$ instead of $mathbb N$.



My question is




How to classify $mathbb N^2$-orbits?




Edit An $mathbb N^2$-set is a set equipped with two commuting endomaps.



Here is the classification of $mathbb N$-orbits up to isomorphism I'd like to generalize to $mathbb N^2$-orbits:



I'll give examples of $mathbb N$-orbits, and claim that any $mathbb N$-orbit is isomorphic to exactly one of the examples.



The first example is $mathbb N$ itself viewed as the orbit of $0$ under the standard successor map $nmapsto n+1$.



The other examples are finite, and come as a two parameter family.



Set $X:={x_0,dots,x_n}$ with $nge0$, let $k$ be an integer such that $0le kle n$, and define $s:Xto X$ by $s(x_0)=x_1,dots,s(x_{n-1})=x_n,s(x_n)=x_k$. (Such an orbit resembles the letter P - or the letter O if $k=0$.)



Let $Y$ be an orbit starting with $yin Y$.



If $Y$ is infinite, $(Y,y)$ is isomorphic to $(mathbb N,0)$ with the usual successor map.



If $Y$ is finite, there is a unique $(k,n)inmathbb N^2$ such that $(Y,y)$ is isomorphic to the orbit $(X,x_0)$ described above.



The verification is left to the reader.







combinatorics elementary-set-theory reference-request category-theory monoid






share|cite|improve this question















share|cite|improve this question













share|cite|improve this question




share|cite|improve this question








edited Dec 31 '18 at 20:21







Pierre-Yves Gaillard

















asked Dec 31 '18 at 16:05









Pierre-Yves GaillardPierre-Yves Gaillard

13.2k23181




13.2k23181












  • What is the "obvious analog"? I can think of a few different ways to define $mathbb{N}^2$-sets.
    – Ben W
    Dec 31 '18 at 16:26










  • Before worrying about $Bbb N^2$-orbits, what would $Bbb N^2$-sets be?
    – Arthur
    Dec 31 '18 at 16:33










  • Would it be correct to say the following? Namely, that an $mathbb N^2$-set is an action of $mathbb N^2$ on a set $X$, meaning a function $mathbb N^2 times X mapsto X$ that associates to each $vec m = (m_1,m_2) in mathbb N^2$ and each $x in X$ an element $vec m cdot x in X$, such that $(vec m + vec n) cdot x = vec m cdot ( vec n cdot x)$.
    – Lee Mosher
    Dec 31 '18 at 16:38






  • 3




    I agree with Lee. I thought that an $M$-set ($M$ a monoid) is a set $X$ equipped with a monoid morphism $Mtotext{End}(X)$. An $mathbb N^2$-set is also given by two commuting endomaps. @BenW
    – Pierre-Yves Gaillard
    Dec 31 '18 at 16:41






  • 4




    @BenW - Yes, $text{End}(X)$ is just mean the set of all maps from $X$ into itself. It's implicit that we're in the category of sets. The analog is that an $mathbb N^2$-set is given by two commuting endomaps.
    – Pierre-Yves Gaillard
    Dec 31 '18 at 18:00


















  • What is the "obvious analog"? I can think of a few different ways to define $mathbb{N}^2$-sets.
    – Ben W
    Dec 31 '18 at 16:26










  • Before worrying about $Bbb N^2$-orbits, what would $Bbb N^2$-sets be?
    – Arthur
    Dec 31 '18 at 16:33










  • Would it be correct to say the following? Namely, that an $mathbb N^2$-set is an action of $mathbb N^2$ on a set $X$, meaning a function $mathbb N^2 times X mapsto X$ that associates to each $vec m = (m_1,m_2) in mathbb N^2$ and each $x in X$ an element $vec m cdot x in X$, such that $(vec m + vec n) cdot x = vec m cdot ( vec n cdot x)$.
    – Lee Mosher
    Dec 31 '18 at 16:38






  • 3




    I agree with Lee. I thought that an $M$-set ($M$ a monoid) is a set $X$ equipped with a monoid morphism $Mtotext{End}(X)$. An $mathbb N^2$-set is also given by two commuting endomaps. @BenW
    – Pierre-Yves Gaillard
    Dec 31 '18 at 16:41






  • 4




    @BenW - Yes, $text{End}(X)$ is just mean the set of all maps from $X$ into itself. It's implicit that we're in the category of sets. The analog is that an $mathbb N^2$-set is given by two commuting endomaps.
    – Pierre-Yves Gaillard
    Dec 31 '18 at 18:00
















What is the "obvious analog"? I can think of a few different ways to define $mathbb{N}^2$-sets.
– Ben W
Dec 31 '18 at 16:26




What is the "obvious analog"? I can think of a few different ways to define $mathbb{N}^2$-sets.
– Ben W
Dec 31 '18 at 16:26












Before worrying about $Bbb N^2$-orbits, what would $Bbb N^2$-sets be?
– Arthur
Dec 31 '18 at 16:33




Before worrying about $Bbb N^2$-orbits, what would $Bbb N^2$-sets be?
– Arthur
Dec 31 '18 at 16:33












Would it be correct to say the following? Namely, that an $mathbb N^2$-set is an action of $mathbb N^2$ on a set $X$, meaning a function $mathbb N^2 times X mapsto X$ that associates to each $vec m = (m_1,m_2) in mathbb N^2$ and each $x in X$ an element $vec m cdot x in X$, such that $(vec m + vec n) cdot x = vec m cdot ( vec n cdot x)$.
– Lee Mosher
Dec 31 '18 at 16:38




Would it be correct to say the following? Namely, that an $mathbb N^2$-set is an action of $mathbb N^2$ on a set $X$, meaning a function $mathbb N^2 times X mapsto X$ that associates to each $vec m = (m_1,m_2) in mathbb N^2$ and each $x in X$ an element $vec m cdot x in X$, such that $(vec m + vec n) cdot x = vec m cdot ( vec n cdot x)$.
– Lee Mosher
Dec 31 '18 at 16:38




3




3




I agree with Lee. I thought that an $M$-set ($M$ a monoid) is a set $X$ equipped with a monoid morphism $Mtotext{End}(X)$. An $mathbb N^2$-set is also given by two commuting endomaps. @BenW
– Pierre-Yves Gaillard
Dec 31 '18 at 16:41




I agree with Lee. I thought that an $M$-set ($M$ a monoid) is a set $X$ equipped with a monoid morphism $Mtotext{End}(X)$. An $mathbb N^2$-set is also given by two commuting endomaps. @BenW
– Pierre-Yves Gaillard
Dec 31 '18 at 16:41




4




4




@BenW - Yes, $text{End}(X)$ is just mean the set of all maps from $X$ into itself. It's implicit that we're in the category of sets. The analog is that an $mathbb N^2$-set is given by two commuting endomaps.
– Pierre-Yves Gaillard
Dec 31 '18 at 18:00




@BenW - Yes, $text{End}(X)$ is just mean the set of all maps from $X$ into itself. It's implicit that we're in the category of sets. The analog is that an $mathbb N^2$-set is given by two commuting endomaps.
– Pierre-Yves Gaillard
Dec 31 '18 at 18:00










3 Answers
3






active

oldest

votes


















1














I'll give a partial answer by trying to answer what the "cyclic" part of sorts can look like.



Let $(Y,y)$ be an $newcommandNN{Bbb{N}}NN^2$-orbit, with $r$ and $s$ the commuting endomaps.



Define a $newcommandZZ{Bbb{Z}}ZZ^2$-set $Z$ by $Z=Ytimes Y/sim$, where $(m,0)$ acts by $r^m$ on the first copy for $m > 0$, $(-m,0)$ acts by $r^m$ on the second copy of $Y$, again with $m> 0$, and $(0,n)$ acts by $s$ on the first or second copy according to its sign. Then the $sim$ relation will be $(y_1,y_2)sim (y_3,y_4)$ if there exist $a,binNN$ such that $r^as^by_1=r^as^by_3$ and $r^as^by_2=r^as^by_4$. It's not hard to check that $sim$ forms an equivalence relation that respects the group action.



Essentially, we're forming the Grothendieck group of the image of $NN^2$ in $operatorname{End}(X)$.



Note that if $a,b,c,dinNN$, then $(a-b,c-d)[(y_1,y_2)]=[(r^as^cy_1,r^bs^dy_2)]$.



This implies that $ZZ^2$ acts transitively on $Z$, since $Y$ is a $NN^2$-orbit:



Let $[(y_1,y_2)]in Z$. Let $y_1 = r^as^b y$ and $y_2 = r^cs^d y$. Then
$[(y_1,y_2)] = (a-c,b-d)[(y,y)]$, so every element of $Z$ is in the orbit of $[(y,y)]$.



Thus $Z$ as a $ZZ^2$-set is isomorphic to $ZZ^2/K$ for some $Ksubseteq ZZ^2$.



In particular, though, we know that $K$ is free of rank 0, 1, or 2.



If $K$ is free of rank 0, $K=0$, and there are no nontrivial relations in $Z$, so there can't be any nontrivial relations in $Y$ either, since you can think of $Z$ as describing the "eventual" behavior of $Y$. Thus if $K=0$, $Y$ is isomorphic to $(NN^2,0)$.



If $K$ is free of rank 1, $K=langle (n,m) rangle$, then $Y$ looks sort of like what you get by rolling up a piece of paper in one direction, but perhaps at an angle to the actual lines of the paper. The starting part is a bit more difficult to work out, but it's eventually cyclic in one direction, and one direction with no cyclicity.



If $K$ is free of rank 2, $Y$ looks sort of like a (discrete) torus, again, the starting part is a bit difficult to work out, but eventually $Y$ sort of looks like a torus, with two directions of cyclicity.



Hopefully this is helpful, and perhaps this can be turned into a complete answer, but I don't have the time right now to figure out a precise statement of the algebraic relationship between $Z$ and $Y$, or to work out what the beginning behavior can look like.



For example, it seems likely that $Y$ could start by getting one direction of cyclicity, and continuing for a while before getting its second direction of cyclicity, forming a sort of P shape, but with a flat part to the left, and where the $P$ shape is made of tubes.



Edit I found a source calling these trajectories instead of orbits (which makes a lot of sense), but I haven't found anything classifying trajectories for $NN^2$






share|cite|improve this answer





























    1














    Let me augment the answer of @jgon, who produces a coarse classification of $mathbb N^2$ orbits according to the corresponding subgroup $K < mathbb Z^2$ and $mathbb Z^2$ set $Z = mathbb Z^2 / K$. That answer also shows that if $K$ has rank $0$ then there is just one corresponding $mathbb N^2$ orbit.



    I'll show that if the subgroup $K < mathbb Z^2$ has rank $1$ or $2$ then there are infinitely many classes of $mathbb N$-orbits corresponding to $K$. Of course, the group $K$ acts on $mathbb Z^2$ by addition,
    $$(k,l) cdot (i,j) = (k+i,l+j) quad text{for each $(k,l) in K$ and $(i,j) in mathbb Z^2$}
    $$

    The $K$-orbit of $(i,j)$ will be denoted
    $$(i,j) + K = {(k+i,l+j) mid (k,l) in K}
    $$

    and the $mathbb Z^2$ set corresponding to $K$ will be denoted
    $$Z = mathbb Z^2 / K = {(i,j) + K mid (i,j) in mathbb Z^2}
    $$



    Basically the idea is to construct an $mathbb N^2$ set $Y = A cup Z$ where $Z$ is the "periodic" part of the action and $A$ is the "preperiodic part" of the action (what @jgon calls the "starting part"). So I have to describe what $A$ can be.



    Let $A subset mathbb N^2$ be a subset which is complement closed with respect to the addition action of $mathbb N^2$ on itself, meaning that for all $(a,b) in mathbb N^2 - A$ and $(m,n) in mathbb N^2$ we have $(a+m,b+n) in mathbb N^2 - A$. For example, here are some complement closed sets:
    $$A = {(1,j) mid j in mathbb N} cup {(i,1) mid i in mathbb N}
    $$

    and
    $$A = {(i,j) in mathbb N^2 mid ij > 42}
    $$

    Now define the $mathbb N^2$ set $Y_A = A cup (mathbb Z^2 / K)$, with the following action of $mathbb N^2$: for each $(m,n) in mathbb N^2$ we have:




    • If $(i,j) + K in mathbb Z^2 / K$ then $(m,n) cdot bigl( (i,j) + K bigr) = (m+i,n+j) + K$

    • If $(i,j) in A$ and $(m+i,n+j) in mathbb N^2 - A$ then $(m,n) cdot (i,j) = bigl( (m+i,n+j) + K bigr)$

    • If $(i,j) in A$ and $(m+i,n+j) in A$ then $(m,n) cdot (i,j) = (m+i,n+j)$


    There are infinitely many complement closed subsets $A subset mathbb N^2$ (at first I thought there were uncountably many different $A$, but now I'm thinking there's only countably many). It's pretty clear that if $K$ is fixed, and if $A_1 ne A_2$ are distinct complement closed sets, then the $mathbb N^2$ sets $Y_{A_1}$ and $Y_{A_2}$ are inequivalent.






    share|cite|improve this answer























    • Very nice! (+1) I wasn't aware of the term preperiodic when I wrote my answer yesterday, hence "starting part," however I chose not to use "periodic" even though cyclic isn't more correct, because the "cyclic" part doesn't have to be periodic in any traditional sense. For example, $Bbb{N}^2$ acting on $Bbb{N}$ by $(x,y)cdot n = n+x+y$ has "cyclic" part $Bbb{Z}^2/langle (1,-1)rangle$, but it's not periodic in any sense, because no nontrivial element of $Bbb{N}^2$ carries any point to itself.
      – jgon
      Jan 1 at 17:42












    • Yeah, "periodic" is being used loosely here, maybe mostly so I could use "preperiodic". Hard to figure out what are the best terms to use for these generalized ideas.
      – Lee Mosher
      Jan 1 at 18:30



















    0














    Edit. In fact every congruence on $mathbb N^n$ is finitely generated. In the book Finitely Generated Commutative Monoids by J. C. Rosales and P. A. García-Sánchez this is stated as Theorem 5.12 page 52, and is called "Rédei's Theorem". This result is sometimes formulated as "Finitely generated commutative monoids are finitely presented". It implies in particular that there are only countably many isomorphism classes of such monoids.



    See also this MathOverflow question by John Baez.



    End of Edit.





    In his answer Lee Mosher asked the question:



    Is the set of all isomorphism classes of $mathbb N^2$ orbits countable?



    I must confess that I hadn't thought of this crucial question. The argument below shows that the answer is Yes.



    Say that an equivalence relation $sim$ on $mathbb N^2$ is a congruence if
    $$
    alphasimbetaimplies alpha+gammasimbeta+gamma.
    $$

    for all $alpha,beta,gammainmathbb N^2$. There is an obvious notion of congruence generated by a relation on $mathbb N^2$.



    If $sim$ is a congruence, $(mathbb N^2/sim,[(0,0)])$ is an $mathbb N^2$-orbit.



    Conversely, if $(X,x_0)$ is an $mathbb N^2$-orbit, and if $f:mathbb N^2to X$ is the unique morphism of $mathbb N^2$-orbits from $(mathbb N^2,(0,0))$ to $(X,x_0)$, then the relation "$f(alpha )=f(beta)$" is a congruence on $mathbb N^2$, and $f$ induces an isomorphism
    $$
    (mathbb N^2/sim,[(0,0)])simeq(X,x_0).
    $$

    The idea behind the following lines is that, if $f(alpha)=f(beta)$, then the behavior of $f$ on the orbit of $beta$ is "the same" as its behavior on the orbit of $alpha$, so that, to know $f$ it suffices to know how it behaves on a single orbit by nonempty fiber.



    Write $text{Orb}(x)$ for the orbit of $x$.



    Lemma. If $alpha_0,alpha_1,dots$ is a sequence of points of $mathbb N^2$, then the ascending chain
    $$
    U_j:=bigcup_{i=0}^jtext{Orb}(alpha_i)
    $$

    stabilizes.



    Proof. Let $m_1$ be the minimum (over $i$) of the $alpha_{i1}$ (with the notation $alpha_i=(alpha_{i1},alpha_{i2})$), define $m_2$ similarly, let $k$ and $ell$ be such that $alpha_{k1}=m_1$ and $alpha_{ell2}=m_2$. Then for $j$ larger than $k$ and $ell$ we have
    $$
    text{Orb}(alpha_k)cuptext{Orb}(alpha_ell)subset U_jsubsettext{Orb}(m_1,m_2).
    $$

    (Here and in the sequel $subset$ means "subset" - not necessarily proper.) As there are only finitely many subsets of $mathbb N^2$ which satisfy the two above inclusions, we are done. $square$



    Claim. Any congruence on $mathbb N^2$ is finitely generated.



    This will answer (in a positive way) Lee Mosher's question.



    Proof. Let $(X,x_0)$ be an $mathbb N^2$-orbit, let $f:mathbb N^2to X$ be the morphism defined above, and let $c:mathbb Ntomathbb N^2$ be the inverse of Cantor's pairing function, so that we have
    $$
    mathbb Nxrightarrow cmathbb N^2xrightarrow fX.
    $$

    We will firstly specify a finite subset $G$ of $(mathbb N^2)^2$ such that $f(alpha)=f(beta)$ for all $(alpha,beta)in G$, and secondly we will define the congruence $sim$ on $mathbb N^2$ as the least congruence such that $alphasim beta$ for all $(alpha,beta)in G$. We'll obviously have $alphasimbetaimplies f(alpha)=f(beta)$, and we'll try to prove the converse implication.



    If $S$ is a subset of $mathbb N$ and if $s:Ito S$ be the only map such that $I$ is an initial segment of $mathbb N$, and $s$ is increasing and surjective, we call $s$ the parametrization of $S$.



    Let $P(mathbb N)$ be the set of subsets of $mathbb N$. We define a map
    $$
    g:P(mathbb N)to(P(mathbb N))^2,quad Smapsto(g_1(S),g_2(S))
    $$

    as follows:



    Let $s:Ito S$ be the parametrization of $S$, so that we have
    $$
    Ixrightarrow sSxrightarrow cmathbb N^2xrightarrow fX; I,Ssubsetmathbb N.
    $$



    If $fcirc ccirc s$ is injective we set $g(S):=(S,varnothing)$.



    Assume $fcirc ccirc s$ is not injective.



    Write $F_isubset I$ for the fiber of $fcirc ccirc s$ containing $iin I$. Let $iin I$ be such that $F_i$ has at least two elements and $i$ is minimum for this condition. Set
    $$
    U:=bigcup_{kin F_isetminus{i}}text{Orb}(c(s(k))).qquad(1)
    $$

    Let $t:Jto F_isubset I$ be the parametrization of $F_i$, so that we have
    $$
    Jxrightarrow tF_ixrightarrow sSxrightarrow cmathbb N^2xrightarrow fX, Jsubsetmathbb N, F_isubset Isubsetmathbb N, Ssubsetmathbb N,
    $$

    and the lemma implies
    $$
    U=bigcup_{j=1}^mtext{Orb}(c(s(t(j))))qquad(2)
    $$

    for some $min Jsubsetmathbb N$. Then we set
    $$
    g_1(S):=c^{-1}(c(S)setminus U),
    $$

    $$
    g_2(S):={s(t(1)),dots,s(t(m))}.
    $$

    Then ends the definition of
    $$
    g:P(mathbb N)to(P(mathbb N))^2,quad Smapsto(g_1(S),g_2(S)).
    $$

    Now we define the subsets
    $$
    mathbb N_0supsetmathbb N_1supsetmathbb N_2supsetcdots
    $$

    inductively by $mathbb N_0:=mathbb N$ and $mathbb N_i:=g_1(mathbb N_{i-1})$ for $ige1$.



    As we remove from $mathbb N^2$ at least one orbit at each stage, the descending chain stabilizes by the lemma, and the union of the $g_2(mathbb N_i)$ is a finite set $K$:
    $$
    K:=bigcup_{iinmathbb N}g_2(mathbb N_i).
    $$

    We define the finite subset
    $$
    Gsubset(mathbb N^2)^2
    $$

    by decreeing that the couple $(alpha,beta)in(mathbb N^2)^2$ is in $G$ if and only if
    $$
    c^{-1}(alpha),c^{-1}(beta)in g_2(mathbb N_i)
    $$

    for some $iinmathbb N$.



    As indicated above, we define the congruence $sim$ on $mathbb N^2$ as the least congruence such that $alphasimbeta$ for all $(alpha,beta)in G$. We obviously have $alphasimbetaimplies f(alpha)=f(beta)$.



    Let us prove $f(alpha)=f(beta)impliesalphasimbeta$.



    We assume by contradiction that there are $i,jinmathbb N$ such that $c(i)notsim c(j)$ but $f(c(i))=f(c(j))$. We also assume that $i+j$ is minimum for this condition.



    As $fcirc c$ is injective on $mathbb N_infty$ (we write $mathbb N_infty$ for the eventual value of the $mathbb N_k$), the integers $i$ and $j$ cannot be both in $mathbb N_infty$. Say that $i$ is not in $mathbb N_infty$. This means that $c(i)$ is in $text{Orb}(c(k))$ for some $kin K$, that is $kin g_2(mathbb N_n)$ for some $ninmathbb N$. Let $m$ be the minimum of $g_2(mathbb N_n)$. We get
    $$
    m<k
    $$

    (this is because we have $kne i$ in $(1)$, or, equivalently, $jge1$ in $(2)$) and $c(m)sim c(k)$ by definition of $sim$. As $c(i)intext{Orb}(c(k))$, we can write
    $$
    c(i)=c(k)+alpha
    $$

    with $alphainmathbb N^2$. Define $i'inmathbb N$ by
    $$
    c(i')=c(m)+alpha.
    $$

    It is easy to see, using the definition of Cantor's pairing function, that the last three displays imply $i'<i$.



    We get $c(i')sim c(i)notsim c(j)$, so that we can replace $(i,j)$ with $(i',j)$, which yields the contradiction $i'+j<i+j$ (recall that $i+j$ was assumed to be minimum).



    This shows that there are no $i,jinmathbb N$ such that $c(i)notsim c(j)$ but $f(c(i))=f(c(j))$, and thus that $f(alpha)=f(beta)iffalphasimbeta$. Therefore $sim$ is an arbitrary congruence, and we proved that it is finitely generated. $square$






    share|cite|improve this answer























      Your Answer





      StackExchange.ifUsing("editor", function () {
      return StackExchange.using("mathjaxEditing", function () {
      StackExchange.MarkdownEditor.creationCallbacks.add(function (editor, postfix) {
      StackExchange.mathjaxEditing.prepareWmdForMathJax(editor, postfix, [["$", "$"], ["\\(","\\)"]]);
      });
      });
      }, "mathjax-editing");

      StackExchange.ready(function() {
      var channelOptions = {
      tags: "".split(" "),
      id: "69"
      };
      initTagRenderer("".split(" "), "".split(" "), channelOptions);

      StackExchange.using("externalEditor", function() {
      // Have to fire editor after snippets, if snippets enabled
      if (StackExchange.settings.snippets.snippetsEnabled) {
      StackExchange.using("snippets", function() {
      createEditor();
      });
      }
      else {
      createEditor();
      }
      });

      function createEditor() {
      StackExchange.prepareEditor({
      heartbeatType: 'answer',
      autoActivateHeartbeat: false,
      convertImagesToLinks: true,
      noModals: true,
      showLowRepImageUploadWarning: true,
      reputationToPostImages: 10,
      bindNavPrevention: true,
      postfix: "",
      imageUploader: {
      brandingHtml: "Powered by u003ca class="icon-imgur-white" href="https://imgur.com/"u003eu003c/au003e",
      contentPolicyHtml: "User contributions licensed under u003ca href="https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-sa/3.0/"u003ecc by-sa 3.0 with attribution requiredu003c/au003e u003ca href="https://stackoverflow.com/legal/content-policy"u003e(content policy)u003c/au003e",
      allowUrls: true
      },
      noCode: true, onDemand: true,
      discardSelector: ".discard-answer"
      ,immediatelyShowMarkdownHelp:true
      });


      }
      });














      draft saved

      draft discarded


















      StackExchange.ready(
      function () {
      StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f3057838%2fhow-to-classify-mathbb-n2-orbits%23new-answer', 'question_page');
      }
      );

      Post as a guest















      Required, but never shown

























      3 Answers
      3






      active

      oldest

      votes








      3 Answers
      3






      active

      oldest

      votes









      active

      oldest

      votes






      active

      oldest

      votes









      1














      I'll give a partial answer by trying to answer what the "cyclic" part of sorts can look like.



      Let $(Y,y)$ be an $newcommandNN{Bbb{N}}NN^2$-orbit, with $r$ and $s$ the commuting endomaps.



      Define a $newcommandZZ{Bbb{Z}}ZZ^2$-set $Z$ by $Z=Ytimes Y/sim$, where $(m,0)$ acts by $r^m$ on the first copy for $m > 0$, $(-m,0)$ acts by $r^m$ on the second copy of $Y$, again with $m> 0$, and $(0,n)$ acts by $s$ on the first or second copy according to its sign. Then the $sim$ relation will be $(y_1,y_2)sim (y_3,y_4)$ if there exist $a,binNN$ such that $r^as^by_1=r^as^by_3$ and $r^as^by_2=r^as^by_4$. It's not hard to check that $sim$ forms an equivalence relation that respects the group action.



      Essentially, we're forming the Grothendieck group of the image of $NN^2$ in $operatorname{End}(X)$.



      Note that if $a,b,c,dinNN$, then $(a-b,c-d)[(y_1,y_2)]=[(r^as^cy_1,r^bs^dy_2)]$.



      This implies that $ZZ^2$ acts transitively on $Z$, since $Y$ is a $NN^2$-orbit:



      Let $[(y_1,y_2)]in Z$. Let $y_1 = r^as^b y$ and $y_2 = r^cs^d y$. Then
      $[(y_1,y_2)] = (a-c,b-d)[(y,y)]$, so every element of $Z$ is in the orbit of $[(y,y)]$.



      Thus $Z$ as a $ZZ^2$-set is isomorphic to $ZZ^2/K$ for some $Ksubseteq ZZ^2$.



      In particular, though, we know that $K$ is free of rank 0, 1, or 2.



      If $K$ is free of rank 0, $K=0$, and there are no nontrivial relations in $Z$, so there can't be any nontrivial relations in $Y$ either, since you can think of $Z$ as describing the "eventual" behavior of $Y$. Thus if $K=0$, $Y$ is isomorphic to $(NN^2,0)$.



      If $K$ is free of rank 1, $K=langle (n,m) rangle$, then $Y$ looks sort of like what you get by rolling up a piece of paper in one direction, but perhaps at an angle to the actual lines of the paper. The starting part is a bit more difficult to work out, but it's eventually cyclic in one direction, and one direction with no cyclicity.



      If $K$ is free of rank 2, $Y$ looks sort of like a (discrete) torus, again, the starting part is a bit difficult to work out, but eventually $Y$ sort of looks like a torus, with two directions of cyclicity.



      Hopefully this is helpful, and perhaps this can be turned into a complete answer, but I don't have the time right now to figure out a precise statement of the algebraic relationship between $Z$ and $Y$, or to work out what the beginning behavior can look like.



      For example, it seems likely that $Y$ could start by getting one direction of cyclicity, and continuing for a while before getting its second direction of cyclicity, forming a sort of P shape, but with a flat part to the left, and where the $P$ shape is made of tubes.



      Edit I found a source calling these trajectories instead of orbits (which makes a lot of sense), but I haven't found anything classifying trajectories for $NN^2$






      share|cite|improve this answer


























        1














        I'll give a partial answer by trying to answer what the "cyclic" part of sorts can look like.



        Let $(Y,y)$ be an $newcommandNN{Bbb{N}}NN^2$-orbit, with $r$ and $s$ the commuting endomaps.



        Define a $newcommandZZ{Bbb{Z}}ZZ^2$-set $Z$ by $Z=Ytimes Y/sim$, where $(m,0)$ acts by $r^m$ on the first copy for $m > 0$, $(-m,0)$ acts by $r^m$ on the second copy of $Y$, again with $m> 0$, and $(0,n)$ acts by $s$ on the first or second copy according to its sign. Then the $sim$ relation will be $(y_1,y_2)sim (y_3,y_4)$ if there exist $a,binNN$ such that $r^as^by_1=r^as^by_3$ and $r^as^by_2=r^as^by_4$. It's not hard to check that $sim$ forms an equivalence relation that respects the group action.



        Essentially, we're forming the Grothendieck group of the image of $NN^2$ in $operatorname{End}(X)$.



        Note that if $a,b,c,dinNN$, then $(a-b,c-d)[(y_1,y_2)]=[(r^as^cy_1,r^bs^dy_2)]$.



        This implies that $ZZ^2$ acts transitively on $Z$, since $Y$ is a $NN^2$-orbit:



        Let $[(y_1,y_2)]in Z$. Let $y_1 = r^as^b y$ and $y_2 = r^cs^d y$. Then
        $[(y_1,y_2)] = (a-c,b-d)[(y,y)]$, so every element of $Z$ is in the orbit of $[(y,y)]$.



        Thus $Z$ as a $ZZ^2$-set is isomorphic to $ZZ^2/K$ for some $Ksubseteq ZZ^2$.



        In particular, though, we know that $K$ is free of rank 0, 1, or 2.



        If $K$ is free of rank 0, $K=0$, and there are no nontrivial relations in $Z$, so there can't be any nontrivial relations in $Y$ either, since you can think of $Z$ as describing the "eventual" behavior of $Y$. Thus if $K=0$, $Y$ is isomorphic to $(NN^2,0)$.



        If $K$ is free of rank 1, $K=langle (n,m) rangle$, then $Y$ looks sort of like what you get by rolling up a piece of paper in one direction, but perhaps at an angle to the actual lines of the paper. The starting part is a bit more difficult to work out, but it's eventually cyclic in one direction, and one direction with no cyclicity.



        If $K$ is free of rank 2, $Y$ looks sort of like a (discrete) torus, again, the starting part is a bit difficult to work out, but eventually $Y$ sort of looks like a torus, with two directions of cyclicity.



        Hopefully this is helpful, and perhaps this can be turned into a complete answer, but I don't have the time right now to figure out a precise statement of the algebraic relationship between $Z$ and $Y$, or to work out what the beginning behavior can look like.



        For example, it seems likely that $Y$ could start by getting one direction of cyclicity, and continuing for a while before getting its second direction of cyclicity, forming a sort of P shape, but with a flat part to the left, and where the $P$ shape is made of tubes.



        Edit I found a source calling these trajectories instead of orbits (which makes a lot of sense), but I haven't found anything classifying trajectories for $NN^2$






        share|cite|improve this answer
























          1












          1








          1






          I'll give a partial answer by trying to answer what the "cyclic" part of sorts can look like.



          Let $(Y,y)$ be an $newcommandNN{Bbb{N}}NN^2$-orbit, with $r$ and $s$ the commuting endomaps.



          Define a $newcommandZZ{Bbb{Z}}ZZ^2$-set $Z$ by $Z=Ytimes Y/sim$, where $(m,0)$ acts by $r^m$ on the first copy for $m > 0$, $(-m,0)$ acts by $r^m$ on the second copy of $Y$, again with $m> 0$, and $(0,n)$ acts by $s$ on the first or second copy according to its sign. Then the $sim$ relation will be $(y_1,y_2)sim (y_3,y_4)$ if there exist $a,binNN$ such that $r^as^by_1=r^as^by_3$ and $r^as^by_2=r^as^by_4$. It's not hard to check that $sim$ forms an equivalence relation that respects the group action.



          Essentially, we're forming the Grothendieck group of the image of $NN^2$ in $operatorname{End}(X)$.



          Note that if $a,b,c,dinNN$, then $(a-b,c-d)[(y_1,y_2)]=[(r^as^cy_1,r^bs^dy_2)]$.



          This implies that $ZZ^2$ acts transitively on $Z$, since $Y$ is a $NN^2$-orbit:



          Let $[(y_1,y_2)]in Z$. Let $y_1 = r^as^b y$ and $y_2 = r^cs^d y$. Then
          $[(y_1,y_2)] = (a-c,b-d)[(y,y)]$, so every element of $Z$ is in the orbit of $[(y,y)]$.



          Thus $Z$ as a $ZZ^2$-set is isomorphic to $ZZ^2/K$ for some $Ksubseteq ZZ^2$.



          In particular, though, we know that $K$ is free of rank 0, 1, or 2.



          If $K$ is free of rank 0, $K=0$, and there are no nontrivial relations in $Z$, so there can't be any nontrivial relations in $Y$ either, since you can think of $Z$ as describing the "eventual" behavior of $Y$. Thus if $K=0$, $Y$ is isomorphic to $(NN^2,0)$.



          If $K$ is free of rank 1, $K=langle (n,m) rangle$, then $Y$ looks sort of like what you get by rolling up a piece of paper in one direction, but perhaps at an angle to the actual lines of the paper. The starting part is a bit more difficult to work out, but it's eventually cyclic in one direction, and one direction with no cyclicity.



          If $K$ is free of rank 2, $Y$ looks sort of like a (discrete) torus, again, the starting part is a bit difficult to work out, but eventually $Y$ sort of looks like a torus, with two directions of cyclicity.



          Hopefully this is helpful, and perhaps this can be turned into a complete answer, but I don't have the time right now to figure out a precise statement of the algebraic relationship between $Z$ and $Y$, or to work out what the beginning behavior can look like.



          For example, it seems likely that $Y$ could start by getting one direction of cyclicity, and continuing for a while before getting its second direction of cyclicity, forming a sort of P shape, but with a flat part to the left, and where the $P$ shape is made of tubes.



          Edit I found a source calling these trajectories instead of orbits (which makes a lot of sense), but I haven't found anything classifying trajectories for $NN^2$






          share|cite|improve this answer












          I'll give a partial answer by trying to answer what the "cyclic" part of sorts can look like.



          Let $(Y,y)$ be an $newcommandNN{Bbb{N}}NN^2$-orbit, with $r$ and $s$ the commuting endomaps.



          Define a $newcommandZZ{Bbb{Z}}ZZ^2$-set $Z$ by $Z=Ytimes Y/sim$, where $(m,0)$ acts by $r^m$ on the first copy for $m > 0$, $(-m,0)$ acts by $r^m$ on the second copy of $Y$, again with $m> 0$, and $(0,n)$ acts by $s$ on the first or second copy according to its sign. Then the $sim$ relation will be $(y_1,y_2)sim (y_3,y_4)$ if there exist $a,binNN$ such that $r^as^by_1=r^as^by_3$ and $r^as^by_2=r^as^by_4$. It's not hard to check that $sim$ forms an equivalence relation that respects the group action.



          Essentially, we're forming the Grothendieck group of the image of $NN^2$ in $operatorname{End}(X)$.



          Note that if $a,b,c,dinNN$, then $(a-b,c-d)[(y_1,y_2)]=[(r^as^cy_1,r^bs^dy_2)]$.



          This implies that $ZZ^2$ acts transitively on $Z$, since $Y$ is a $NN^2$-orbit:



          Let $[(y_1,y_2)]in Z$. Let $y_1 = r^as^b y$ and $y_2 = r^cs^d y$. Then
          $[(y_1,y_2)] = (a-c,b-d)[(y,y)]$, so every element of $Z$ is in the orbit of $[(y,y)]$.



          Thus $Z$ as a $ZZ^2$-set is isomorphic to $ZZ^2/K$ for some $Ksubseteq ZZ^2$.



          In particular, though, we know that $K$ is free of rank 0, 1, or 2.



          If $K$ is free of rank 0, $K=0$, and there are no nontrivial relations in $Z$, so there can't be any nontrivial relations in $Y$ either, since you can think of $Z$ as describing the "eventual" behavior of $Y$. Thus if $K=0$, $Y$ is isomorphic to $(NN^2,0)$.



          If $K$ is free of rank 1, $K=langle (n,m) rangle$, then $Y$ looks sort of like what you get by rolling up a piece of paper in one direction, but perhaps at an angle to the actual lines of the paper. The starting part is a bit more difficult to work out, but it's eventually cyclic in one direction, and one direction with no cyclicity.



          If $K$ is free of rank 2, $Y$ looks sort of like a (discrete) torus, again, the starting part is a bit difficult to work out, but eventually $Y$ sort of looks like a torus, with two directions of cyclicity.



          Hopefully this is helpful, and perhaps this can be turned into a complete answer, but I don't have the time right now to figure out a precise statement of the algebraic relationship between $Z$ and $Y$, or to work out what the beginning behavior can look like.



          For example, it seems likely that $Y$ could start by getting one direction of cyclicity, and continuing for a while before getting its second direction of cyclicity, forming a sort of P shape, but with a flat part to the left, and where the $P$ shape is made of tubes.



          Edit I found a source calling these trajectories instead of orbits (which makes a lot of sense), but I haven't found anything classifying trajectories for $NN^2$







          share|cite|improve this answer












          share|cite|improve this answer



          share|cite|improve this answer










          answered Dec 31 '18 at 21:29









          jgonjgon

          13.4k22041




          13.4k22041























              1














              Let me augment the answer of @jgon, who produces a coarse classification of $mathbb N^2$ orbits according to the corresponding subgroup $K < mathbb Z^2$ and $mathbb Z^2$ set $Z = mathbb Z^2 / K$. That answer also shows that if $K$ has rank $0$ then there is just one corresponding $mathbb N^2$ orbit.



              I'll show that if the subgroup $K < mathbb Z^2$ has rank $1$ or $2$ then there are infinitely many classes of $mathbb N$-orbits corresponding to $K$. Of course, the group $K$ acts on $mathbb Z^2$ by addition,
              $$(k,l) cdot (i,j) = (k+i,l+j) quad text{for each $(k,l) in K$ and $(i,j) in mathbb Z^2$}
              $$

              The $K$-orbit of $(i,j)$ will be denoted
              $$(i,j) + K = {(k+i,l+j) mid (k,l) in K}
              $$

              and the $mathbb Z^2$ set corresponding to $K$ will be denoted
              $$Z = mathbb Z^2 / K = {(i,j) + K mid (i,j) in mathbb Z^2}
              $$



              Basically the idea is to construct an $mathbb N^2$ set $Y = A cup Z$ where $Z$ is the "periodic" part of the action and $A$ is the "preperiodic part" of the action (what @jgon calls the "starting part"). So I have to describe what $A$ can be.



              Let $A subset mathbb N^2$ be a subset which is complement closed with respect to the addition action of $mathbb N^2$ on itself, meaning that for all $(a,b) in mathbb N^2 - A$ and $(m,n) in mathbb N^2$ we have $(a+m,b+n) in mathbb N^2 - A$. For example, here are some complement closed sets:
              $$A = {(1,j) mid j in mathbb N} cup {(i,1) mid i in mathbb N}
              $$

              and
              $$A = {(i,j) in mathbb N^2 mid ij > 42}
              $$

              Now define the $mathbb N^2$ set $Y_A = A cup (mathbb Z^2 / K)$, with the following action of $mathbb N^2$: for each $(m,n) in mathbb N^2$ we have:




              • If $(i,j) + K in mathbb Z^2 / K$ then $(m,n) cdot bigl( (i,j) + K bigr) = (m+i,n+j) + K$

              • If $(i,j) in A$ and $(m+i,n+j) in mathbb N^2 - A$ then $(m,n) cdot (i,j) = bigl( (m+i,n+j) + K bigr)$

              • If $(i,j) in A$ and $(m+i,n+j) in A$ then $(m,n) cdot (i,j) = (m+i,n+j)$


              There are infinitely many complement closed subsets $A subset mathbb N^2$ (at first I thought there were uncountably many different $A$, but now I'm thinking there's only countably many). It's pretty clear that if $K$ is fixed, and if $A_1 ne A_2$ are distinct complement closed sets, then the $mathbb N^2$ sets $Y_{A_1}$ and $Y_{A_2}$ are inequivalent.






              share|cite|improve this answer























              • Very nice! (+1) I wasn't aware of the term preperiodic when I wrote my answer yesterday, hence "starting part," however I chose not to use "periodic" even though cyclic isn't more correct, because the "cyclic" part doesn't have to be periodic in any traditional sense. For example, $Bbb{N}^2$ acting on $Bbb{N}$ by $(x,y)cdot n = n+x+y$ has "cyclic" part $Bbb{Z}^2/langle (1,-1)rangle$, but it's not periodic in any sense, because no nontrivial element of $Bbb{N}^2$ carries any point to itself.
                – jgon
                Jan 1 at 17:42












              • Yeah, "periodic" is being used loosely here, maybe mostly so I could use "preperiodic". Hard to figure out what are the best terms to use for these generalized ideas.
                – Lee Mosher
                Jan 1 at 18:30
















              1














              Let me augment the answer of @jgon, who produces a coarse classification of $mathbb N^2$ orbits according to the corresponding subgroup $K < mathbb Z^2$ and $mathbb Z^2$ set $Z = mathbb Z^2 / K$. That answer also shows that if $K$ has rank $0$ then there is just one corresponding $mathbb N^2$ orbit.



              I'll show that if the subgroup $K < mathbb Z^2$ has rank $1$ or $2$ then there are infinitely many classes of $mathbb N$-orbits corresponding to $K$. Of course, the group $K$ acts on $mathbb Z^2$ by addition,
              $$(k,l) cdot (i,j) = (k+i,l+j) quad text{for each $(k,l) in K$ and $(i,j) in mathbb Z^2$}
              $$

              The $K$-orbit of $(i,j)$ will be denoted
              $$(i,j) + K = {(k+i,l+j) mid (k,l) in K}
              $$

              and the $mathbb Z^2$ set corresponding to $K$ will be denoted
              $$Z = mathbb Z^2 / K = {(i,j) + K mid (i,j) in mathbb Z^2}
              $$



              Basically the idea is to construct an $mathbb N^2$ set $Y = A cup Z$ where $Z$ is the "periodic" part of the action and $A$ is the "preperiodic part" of the action (what @jgon calls the "starting part"). So I have to describe what $A$ can be.



              Let $A subset mathbb N^2$ be a subset which is complement closed with respect to the addition action of $mathbb N^2$ on itself, meaning that for all $(a,b) in mathbb N^2 - A$ and $(m,n) in mathbb N^2$ we have $(a+m,b+n) in mathbb N^2 - A$. For example, here are some complement closed sets:
              $$A = {(1,j) mid j in mathbb N} cup {(i,1) mid i in mathbb N}
              $$

              and
              $$A = {(i,j) in mathbb N^2 mid ij > 42}
              $$

              Now define the $mathbb N^2$ set $Y_A = A cup (mathbb Z^2 / K)$, with the following action of $mathbb N^2$: for each $(m,n) in mathbb N^2$ we have:




              • If $(i,j) + K in mathbb Z^2 / K$ then $(m,n) cdot bigl( (i,j) + K bigr) = (m+i,n+j) + K$

              • If $(i,j) in A$ and $(m+i,n+j) in mathbb N^2 - A$ then $(m,n) cdot (i,j) = bigl( (m+i,n+j) + K bigr)$

              • If $(i,j) in A$ and $(m+i,n+j) in A$ then $(m,n) cdot (i,j) = (m+i,n+j)$


              There are infinitely many complement closed subsets $A subset mathbb N^2$ (at first I thought there were uncountably many different $A$, but now I'm thinking there's only countably many). It's pretty clear that if $K$ is fixed, and if $A_1 ne A_2$ are distinct complement closed sets, then the $mathbb N^2$ sets $Y_{A_1}$ and $Y_{A_2}$ are inequivalent.






              share|cite|improve this answer























              • Very nice! (+1) I wasn't aware of the term preperiodic when I wrote my answer yesterday, hence "starting part," however I chose not to use "periodic" even though cyclic isn't more correct, because the "cyclic" part doesn't have to be periodic in any traditional sense. For example, $Bbb{N}^2$ acting on $Bbb{N}$ by $(x,y)cdot n = n+x+y$ has "cyclic" part $Bbb{Z}^2/langle (1,-1)rangle$, but it's not periodic in any sense, because no nontrivial element of $Bbb{N}^2$ carries any point to itself.
                – jgon
                Jan 1 at 17:42












              • Yeah, "periodic" is being used loosely here, maybe mostly so I could use "preperiodic". Hard to figure out what are the best terms to use for these generalized ideas.
                – Lee Mosher
                Jan 1 at 18:30














              1












              1








              1






              Let me augment the answer of @jgon, who produces a coarse classification of $mathbb N^2$ orbits according to the corresponding subgroup $K < mathbb Z^2$ and $mathbb Z^2$ set $Z = mathbb Z^2 / K$. That answer also shows that if $K$ has rank $0$ then there is just one corresponding $mathbb N^2$ orbit.



              I'll show that if the subgroup $K < mathbb Z^2$ has rank $1$ or $2$ then there are infinitely many classes of $mathbb N$-orbits corresponding to $K$. Of course, the group $K$ acts on $mathbb Z^2$ by addition,
              $$(k,l) cdot (i,j) = (k+i,l+j) quad text{for each $(k,l) in K$ and $(i,j) in mathbb Z^2$}
              $$

              The $K$-orbit of $(i,j)$ will be denoted
              $$(i,j) + K = {(k+i,l+j) mid (k,l) in K}
              $$

              and the $mathbb Z^2$ set corresponding to $K$ will be denoted
              $$Z = mathbb Z^2 / K = {(i,j) + K mid (i,j) in mathbb Z^2}
              $$



              Basically the idea is to construct an $mathbb N^2$ set $Y = A cup Z$ where $Z$ is the "periodic" part of the action and $A$ is the "preperiodic part" of the action (what @jgon calls the "starting part"). So I have to describe what $A$ can be.



              Let $A subset mathbb N^2$ be a subset which is complement closed with respect to the addition action of $mathbb N^2$ on itself, meaning that for all $(a,b) in mathbb N^2 - A$ and $(m,n) in mathbb N^2$ we have $(a+m,b+n) in mathbb N^2 - A$. For example, here are some complement closed sets:
              $$A = {(1,j) mid j in mathbb N} cup {(i,1) mid i in mathbb N}
              $$

              and
              $$A = {(i,j) in mathbb N^2 mid ij > 42}
              $$

              Now define the $mathbb N^2$ set $Y_A = A cup (mathbb Z^2 / K)$, with the following action of $mathbb N^2$: for each $(m,n) in mathbb N^2$ we have:




              • If $(i,j) + K in mathbb Z^2 / K$ then $(m,n) cdot bigl( (i,j) + K bigr) = (m+i,n+j) + K$

              • If $(i,j) in A$ and $(m+i,n+j) in mathbb N^2 - A$ then $(m,n) cdot (i,j) = bigl( (m+i,n+j) + K bigr)$

              • If $(i,j) in A$ and $(m+i,n+j) in A$ then $(m,n) cdot (i,j) = (m+i,n+j)$


              There are infinitely many complement closed subsets $A subset mathbb N^2$ (at first I thought there were uncountably many different $A$, but now I'm thinking there's only countably many). It's pretty clear that if $K$ is fixed, and if $A_1 ne A_2$ are distinct complement closed sets, then the $mathbb N^2$ sets $Y_{A_1}$ and $Y_{A_2}$ are inequivalent.






              share|cite|improve this answer














              Let me augment the answer of @jgon, who produces a coarse classification of $mathbb N^2$ orbits according to the corresponding subgroup $K < mathbb Z^2$ and $mathbb Z^2$ set $Z = mathbb Z^2 / K$. That answer also shows that if $K$ has rank $0$ then there is just one corresponding $mathbb N^2$ orbit.



              I'll show that if the subgroup $K < mathbb Z^2$ has rank $1$ or $2$ then there are infinitely many classes of $mathbb N$-orbits corresponding to $K$. Of course, the group $K$ acts on $mathbb Z^2$ by addition,
              $$(k,l) cdot (i,j) = (k+i,l+j) quad text{for each $(k,l) in K$ and $(i,j) in mathbb Z^2$}
              $$

              The $K$-orbit of $(i,j)$ will be denoted
              $$(i,j) + K = {(k+i,l+j) mid (k,l) in K}
              $$

              and the $mathbb Z^2$ set corresponding to $K$ will be denoted
              $$Z = mathbb Z^2 / K = {(i,j) + K mid (i,j) in mathbb Z^2}
              $$



              Basically the idea is to construct an $mathbb N^2$ set $Y = A cup Z$ where $Z$ is the "periodic" part of the action and $A$ is the "preperiodic part" of the action (what @jgon calls the "starting part"). So I have to describe what $A$ can be.



              Let $A subset mathbb N^2$ be a subset which is complement closed with respect to the addition action of $mathbb N^2$ on itself, meaning that for all $(a,b) in mathbb N^2 - A$ and $(m,n) in mathbb N^2$ we have $(a+m,b+n) in mathbb N^2 - A$. For example, here are some complement closed sets:
              $$A = {(1,j) mid j in mathbb N} cup {(i,1) mid i in mathbb N}
              $$

              and
              $$A = {(i,j) in mathbb N^2 mid ij > 42}
              $$

              Now define the $mathbb N^2$ set $Y_A = A cup (mathbb Z^2 / K)$, with the following action of $mathbb N^2$: for each $(m,n) in mathbb N^2$ we have:




              • If $(i,j) + K in mathbb Z^2 / K$ then $(m,n) cdot bigl( (i,j) + K bigr) = (m+i,n+j) + K$

              • If $(i,j) in A$ and $(m+i,n+j) in mathbb N^2 - A$ then $(m,n) cdot (i,j) = bigl( (m+i,n+j) + K bigr)$

              • If $(i,j) in A$ and $(m+i,n+j) in A$ then $(m,n) cdot (i,j) = (m+i,n+j)$


              There are infinitely many complement closed subsets $A subset mathbb N^2$ (at first I thought there were uncountably many different $A$, but now I'm thinking there's only countably many). It's pretty clear that if $K$ is fixed, and if $A_1 ne A_2$ are distinct complement closed sets, then the $mathbb N^2$ sets $Y_{A_1}$ and $Y_{A_2}$ are inequivalent.







              share|cite|improve this answer














              share|cite|improve this answer



              share|cite|improve this answer








              edited Jan 1 at 16:57

























              answered Jan 1 at 16:39









              Lee MosherLee Mosher

              48.2k33681




              48.2k33681












              • Very nice! (+1) I wasn't aware of the term preperiodic when I wrote my answer yesterday, hence "starting part," however I chose not to use "periodic" even though cyclic isn't more correct, because the "cyclic" part doesn't have to be periodic in any traditional sense. For example, $Bbb{N}^2$ acting on $Bbb{N}$ by $(x,y)cdot n = n+x+y$ has "cyclic" part $Bbb{Z}^2/langle (1,-1)rangle$, but it's not periodic in any sense, because no nontrivial element of $Bbb{N}^2$ carries any point to itself.
                – jgon
                Jan 1 at 17:42












              • Yeah, "periodic" is being used loosely here, maybe mostly so I could use "preperiodic". Hard to figure out what are the best terms to use for these generalized ideas.
                – Lee Mosher
                Jan 1 at 18:30


















              • Very nice! (+1) I wasn't aware of the term preperiodic when I wrote my answer yesterday, hence "starting part," however I chose not to use "periodic" even though cyclic isn't more correct, because the "cyclic" part doesn't have to be periodic in any traditional sense. For example, $Bbb{N}^2$ acting on $Bbb{N}$ by $(x,y)cdot n = n+x+y$ has "cyclic" part $Bbb{Z}^2/langle (1,-1)rangle$, but it's not periodic in any sense, because no nontrivial element of $Bbb{N}^2$ carries any point to itself.
                – jgon
                Jan 1 at 17:42












              • Yeah, "periodic" is being used loosely here, maybe mostly so I could use "preperiodic". Hard to figure out what are the best terms to use for these generalized ideas.
                – Lee Mosher
                Jan 1 at 18:30
















              Very nice! (+1) I wasn't aware of the term preperiodic when I wrote my answer yesterday, hence "starting part," however I chose not to use "periodic" even though cyclic isn't more correct, because the "cyclic" part doesn't have to be periodic in any traditional sense. For example, $Bbb{N}^2$ acting on $Bbb{N}$ by $(x,y)cdot n = n+x+y$ has "cyclic" part $Bbb{Z}^2/langle (1,-1)rangle$, but it's not periodic in any sense, because no nontrivial element of $Bbb{N}^2$ carries any point to itself.
              – jgon
              Jan 1 at 17:42






              Very nice! (+1) I wasn't aware of the term preperiodic when I wrote my answer yesterday, hence "starting part," however I chose not to use "periodic" even though cyclic isn't more correct, because the "cyclic" part doesn't have to be periodic in any traditional sense. For example, $Bbb{N}^2$ acting on $Bbb{N}$ by $(x,y)cdot n = n+x+y$ has "cyclic" part $Bbb{Z}^2/langle (1,-1)rangle$, but it's not periodic in any sense, because no nontrivial element of $Bbb{N}^2$ carries any point to itself.
              – jgon
              Jan 1 at 17:42














              Yeah, "periodic" is being used loosely here, maybe mostly so I could use "preperiodic". Hard to figure out what are the best terms to use for these generalized ideas.
              – Lee Mosher
              Jan 1 at 18:30




              Yeah, "periodic" is being used loosely here, maybe mostly so I could use "preperiodic". Hard to figure out what are the best terms to use for these generalized ideas.
              – Lee Mosher
              Jan 1 at 18:30











              0














              Edit. In fact every congruence on $mathbb N^n$ is finitely generated. In the book Finitely Generated Commutative Monoids by J. C. Rosales and P. A. García-Sánchez this is stated as Theorem 5.12 page 52, and is called "Rédei's Theorem". This result is sometimes formulated as "Finitely generated commutative monoids are finitely presented". It implies in particular that there are only countably many isomorphism classes of such monoids.



              See also this MathOverflow question by John Baez.



              End of Edit.





              In his answer Lee Mosher asked the question:



              Is the set of all isomorphism classes of $mathbb N^2$ orbits countable?



              I must confess that I hadn't thought of this crucial question. The argument below shows that the answer is Yes.



              Say that an equivalence relation $sim$ on $mathbb N^2$ is a congruence if
              $$
              alphasimbetaimplies alpha+gammasimbeta+gamma.
              $$

              for all $alpha,beta,gammainmathbb N^2$. There is an obvious notion of congruence generated by a relation on $mathbb N^2$.



              If $sim$ is a congruence, $(mathbb N^2/sim,[(0,0)])$ is an $mathbb N^2$-orbit.



              Conversely, if $(X,x_0)$ is an $mathbb N^2$-orbit, and if $f:mathbb N^2to X$ is the unique morphism of $mathbb N^2$-orbits from $(mathbb N^2,(0,0))$ to $(X,x_0)$, then the relation "$f(alpha )=f(beta)$" is a congruence on $mathbb N^2$, and $f$ induces an isomorphism
              $$
              (mathbb N^2/sim,[(0,0)])simeq(X,x_0).
              $$

              The idea behind the following lines is that, if $f(alpha)=f(beta)$, then the behavior of $f$ on the orbit of $beta$ is "the same" as its behavior on the orbit of $alpha$, so that, to know $f$ it suffices to know how it behaves on a single orbit by nonempty fiber.



              Write $text{Orb}(x)$ for the orbit of $x$.



              Lemma. If $alpha_0,alpha_1,dots$ is a sequence of points of $mathbb N^2$, then the ascending chain
              $$
              U_j:=bigcup_{i=0}^jtext{Orb}(alpha_i)
              $$

              stabilizes.



              Proof. Let $m_1$ be the minimum (over $i$) of the $alpha_{i1}$ (with the notation $alpha_i=(alpha_{i1},alpha_{i2})$), define $m_2$ similarly, let $k$ and $ell$ be such that $alpha_{k1}=m_1$ and $alpha_{ell2}=m_2$. Then for $j$ larger than $k$ and $ell$ we have
              $$
              text{Orb}(alpha_k)cuptext{Orb}(alpha_ell)subset U_jsubsettext{Orb}(m_1,m_2).
              $$

              (Here and in the sequel $subset$ means "subset" - not necessarily proper.) As there are only finitely many subsets of $mathbb N^2$ which satisfy the two above inclusions, we are done. $square$



              Claim. Any congruence on $mathbb N^2$ is finitely generated.



              This will answer (in a positive way) Lee Mosher's question.



              Proof. Let $(X,x_0)$ be an $mathbb N^2$-orbit, let $f:mathbb N^2to X$ be the morphism defined above, and let $c:mathbb Ntomathbb N^2$ be the inverse of Cantor's pairing function, so that we have
              $$
              mathbb Nxrightarrow cmathbb N^2xrightarrow fX.
              $$

              We will firstly specify a finite subset $G$ of $(mathbb N^2)^2$ such that $f(alpha)=f(beta)$ for all $(alpha,beta)in G$, and secondly we will define the congruence $sim$ on $mathbb N^2$ as the least congruence such that $alphasim beta$ for all $(alpha,beta)in G$. We'll obviously have $alphasimbetaimplies f(alpha)=f(beta)$, and we'll try to prove the converse implication.



              If $S$ is a subset of $mathbb N$ and if $s:Ito S$ be the only map such that $I$ is an initial segment of $mathbb N$, and $s$ is increasing and surjective, we call $s$ the parametrization of $S$.



              Let $P(mathbb N)$ be the set of subsets of $mathbb N$. We define a map
              $$
              g:P(mathbb N)to(P(mathbb N))^2,quad Smapsto(g_1(S),g_2(S))
              $$

              as follows:



              Let $s:Ito S$ be the parametrization of $S$, so that we have
              $$
              Ixrightarrow sSxrightarrow cmathbb N^2xrightarrow fX; I,Ssubsetmathbb N.
              $$



              If $fcirc ccirc s$ is injective we set $g(S):=(S,varnothing)$.



              Assume $fcirc ccirc s$ is not injective.



              Write $F_isubset I$ for the fiber of $fcirc ccirc s$ containing $iin I$. Let $iin I$ be such that $F_i$ has at least two elements and $i$ is minimum for this condition. Set
              $$
              U:=bigcup_{kin F_isetminus{i}}text{Orb}(c(s(k))).qquad(1)
              $$

              Let $t:Jto F_isubset I$ be the parametrization of $F_i$, so that we have
              $$
              Jxrightarrow tF_ixrightarrow sSxrightarrow cmathbb N^2xrightarrow fX, Jsubsetmathbb N, F_isubset Isubsetmathbb N, Ssubsetmathbb N,
              $$

              and the lemma implies
              $$
              U=bigcup_{j=1}^mtext{Orb}(c(s(t(j))))qquad(2)
              $$

              for some $min Jsubsetmathbb N$. Then we set
              $$
              g_1(S):=c^{-1}(c(S)setminus U),
              $$

              $$
              g_2(S):={s(t(1)),dots,s(t(m))}.
              $$

              Then ends the definition of
              $$
              g:P(mathbb N)to(P(mathbb N))^2,quad Smapsto(g_1(S),g_2(S)).
              $$

              Now we define the subsets
              $$
              mathbb N_0supsetmathbb N_1supsetmathbb N_2supsetcdots
              $$

              inductively by $mathbb N_0:=mathbb N$ and $mathbb N_i:=g_1(mathbb N_{i-1})$ for $ige1$.



              As we remove from $mathbb N^2$ at least one orbit at each stage, the descending chain stabilizes by the lemma, and the union of the $g_2(mathbb N_i)$ is a finite set $K$:
              $$
              K:=bigcup_{iinmathbb N}g_2(mathbb N_i).
              $$

              We define the finite subset
              $$
              Gsubset(mathbb N^2)^2
              $$

              by decreeing that the couple $(alpha,beta)in(mathbb N^2)^2$ is in $G$ if and only if
              $$
              c^{-1}(alpha),c^{-1}(beta)in g_2(mathbb N_i)
              $$

              for some $iinmathbb N$.



              As indicated above, we define the congruence $sim$ on $mathbb N^2$ as the least congruence such that $alphasimbeta$ for all $(alpha,beta)in G$. We obviously have $alphasimbetaimplies f(alpha)=f(beta)$.



              Let us prove $f(alpha)=f(beta)impliesalphasimbeta$.



              We assume by contradiction that there are $i,jinmathbb N$ such that $c(i)notsim c(j)$ but $f(c(i))=f(c(j))$. We also assume that $i+j$ is minimum for this condition.



              As $fcirc c$ is injective on $mathbb N_infty$ (we write $mathbb N_infty$ for the eventual value of the $mathbb N_k$), the integers $i$ and $j$ cannot be both in $mathbb N_infty$. Say that $i$ is not in $mathbb N_infty$. This means that $c(i)$ is in $text{Orb}(c(k))$ for some $kin K$, that is $kin g_2(mathbb N_n)$ for some $ninmathbb N$. Let $m$ be the minimum of $g_2(mathbb N_n)$. We get
              $$
              m<k
              $$

              (this is because we have $kne i$ in $(1)$, or, equivalently, $jge1$ in $(2)$) and $c(m)sim c(k)$ by definition of $sim$. As $c(i)intext{Orb}(c(k))$, we can write
              $$
              c(i)=c(k)+alpha
              $$

              with $alphainmathbb N^2$. Define $i'inmathbb N$ by
              $$
              c(i')=c(m)+alpha.
              $$

              It is easy to see, using the definition of Cantor's pairing function, that the last three displays imply $i'<i$.



              We get $c(i')sim c(i)notsim c(j)$, so that we can replace $(i,j)$ with $(i',j)$, which yields the contradiction $i'+j<i+j$ (recall that $i+j$ was assumed to be minimum).



              This shows that there are no $i,jinmathbb N$ such that $c(i)notsim c(j)$ but $f(c(i))=f(c(j))$, and thus that $f(alpha)=f(beta)iffalphasimbeta$. Therefore $sim$ is an arbitrary congruence, and we proved that it is finitely generated. $square$






              share|cite|improve this answer




























                0














                Edit. In fact every congruence on $mathbb N^n$ is finitely generated. In the book Finitely Generated Commutative Monoids by J. C. Rosales and P. A. García-Sánchez this is stated as Theorem 5.12 page 52, and is called "Rédei's Theorem". This result is sometimes formulated as "Finitely generated commutative monoids are finitely presented". It implies in particular that there are only countably many isomorphism classes of such monoids.



                See also this MathOverflow question by John Baez.



                End of Edit.





                In his answer Lee Mosher asked the question:



                Is the set of all isomorphism classes of $mathbb N^2$ orbits countable?



                I must confess that I hadn't thought of this crucial question. The argument below shows that the answer is Yes.



                Say that an equivalence relation $sim$ on $mathbb N^2$ is a congruence if
                $$
                alphasimbetaimplies alpha+gammasimbeta+gamma.
                $$

                for all $alpha,beta,gammainmathbb N^2$. There is an obvious notion of congruence generated by a relation on $mathbb N^2$.



                If $sim$ is a congruence, $(mathbb N^2/sim,[(0,0)])$ is an $mathbb N^2$-orbit.



                Conversely, if $(X,x_0)$ is an $mathbb N^2$-orbit, and if $f:mathbb N^2to X$ is the unique morphism of $mathbb N^2$-orbits from $(mathbb N^2,(0,0))$ to $(X,x_0)$, then the relation "$f(alpha )=f(beta)$" is a congruence on $mathbb N^2$, and $f$ induces an isomorphism
                $$
                (mathbb N^2/sim,[(0,0)])simeq(X,x_0).
                $$

                The idea behind the following lines is that, if $f(alpha)=f(beta)$, then the behavior of $f$ on the orbit of $beta$ is "the same" as its behavior on the orbit of $alpha$, so that, to know $f$ it suffices to know how it behaves on a single orbit by nonempty fiber.



                Write $text{Orb}(x)$ for the orbit of $x$.



                Lemma. If $alpha_0,alpha_1,dots$ is a sequence of points of $mathbb N^2$, then the ascending chain
                $$
                U_j:=bigcup_{i=0}^jtext{Orb}(alpha_i)
                $$

                stabilizes.



                Proof. Let $m_1$ be the minimum (over $i$) of the $alpha_{i1}$ (with the notation $alpha_i=(alpha_{i1},alpha_{i2})$), define $m_2$ similarly, let $k$ and $ell$ be such that $alpha_{k1}=m_1$ and $alpha_{ell2}=m_2$. Then for $j$ larger than $k$ and $ell$ we have
                $$
                text{Orb}(alpha_k)cuptext{Orb}(alpha_ell)subset U_jsubsettext{Orb}(m_1,m_2).
                $$

                (Here and in the sequel $subset$ means "subset" - not necessarily proper.) As there are only finitely many subsets of $mathbb N^2$ which satisfy the two above inclusions, we are done. $square$



                Claim. Any congruence on $mathbb N^2$ is finitely generated.



                This will answer (in a positive way) Lee Mosher's question.



                Proof. Let $(X,x_0)$ be an $mathbb N^2$-orbit, let $f:mathbb N^2to X$ be the morphism defined above, and let $c:mathbb Ntomathbb N^2$ be the inverse of Cantor's pairing function, so that we have
                $$
                mathbb Nxrightarrow cmathbb N^2xrightarrow fX.
                $$

                We will firstly specify a finite subset $G$ of $(mathbb N^2)^2$ such that $f(alpha)=f(beta)$ for all $(alpha,beta)in G$, and secondly we will define the congruence $sim$ on $mathbb N^2$ as the least congruence such that $alphasim beta$ for all $(alpha,beta)in G$. We'll obviously have $alphasimbetaimplies f(alpha)=f(beta)$, and we'll try to prove the converse implication.



                If $S$ is a subset of $mathbb N$ and if $s:Ito S$ be the only map such that $I$ is an initial segment of $mathbb N$, and $s$ is increasing and surjective, we call $s$ the parametrization of $S$.



                Let $P(mathbb N)$ be the set of subsets of $mathbb N$. We define a map
                $$
                g:P(mathbb N)to(P(mathbb N))^2,quad Smapsto(g_1(S),g_2(S))
                $$

                as follows:



                Let $s:Ito S$ be the parametrization of $S$, so that we have
                $$
                Ixrightarrow sSxrightarrow cmathbb N^2xrightarrow fX; I,Ssubsetmathbb N.
                $$



                If $fcirc ccirc s$ is injective we set $g(S):=(S,varnothing)$.



                Assume $fcirc ccirc s$ is not injective.



                Write $F_isubset I$ for the fiber of $fcirc ccirc s$ containing $iin I$. Let $iin I$ be such that $F_i$ has at least two elements and $i$ is minimum for this condition. Set
                $$
                U:=bigcup_{kin F_isetminus{i}}text{Orb}(c(s(k))).qquad(1)
                $$

                Let $t:Jto F_isubset I$ be the parametrization of $F_i$, so that we have
                $$
                Jxrightarrow tF_ixrightarrow sSxrightarrow cmathbb N^2xrightarrow fX, Jsubsetmathbb N, F_isubset Isubsetmathbb N, Ssubsetmathbb N,
                $$

                and the lemma implies
                $$
                U=bigcup_{j=1}^mtext{Orb}(c(s(t(j))))qquad(2)
                $$

                for some $min Jsubsetmathbb N$. Then we set
                $$
                g_1(S):=c^{-1}(c(S)setminus U),
                $$

                $$
                g_2(S):={s(t(1)),dots,s(t(m))}.
                $$

                Then ends the definition of
                $$
                g:P(mathbb N)to(P(mathbb N))^2,quad Smapsto(g_1(S),g_2(S)).
                $$

                Now we define the subsets
                $$
                mathbb N_0supsetmathbb N_1supsetmathbb N_2supsetcdots
                $$

                inductively by $mathbb N_0:=mathbb N$ and $mathbb N_i:=g_1(mathbb N_{i-1})$ for $ige1$.



                As we remove from $mathbb N^2$ at least one orbit at each stage, the descending chain stabilizes by the lemma, and the union of the $g_2(mathbb N_i)$ is a finite set $K$:
                $$
                K:=bigcup_{iinmathbb N}g_2(mathbb N_i).
                $$

                We define the finite subset
                $$
                Gsubset(mathbb N^2)^2
                $$

                by decreeing that the couple $(alpha,beta)in(mathbb N^2)^2$ is in $G$ if and only if
                $$
                c^{-1}(alpha),c^{-1}(beta)in g_2(mathbb N_i)
                $$

                for some $iinmathbb N$.



                As indicated above, we define the congruence $sim$ on $mathbb N^2$ as the least congruence such that $alphasimbeta$ for all $(alpha,beta)in G$. We obviously have $alphasimbetaimplies f(alpha)=f(beta)$.



                Let us prove $f(alpha)=f(beta)impliesalphasimbeta$.



                We assume by contradiction that there are $i,jinmathbb N$ such that $c(i)notsim c(j)$ but $f(c(i))=f(c(j))$. We also assume that $i+j$ is minimum for this condition.



                As $fcirc c$ is injective on $mathbb N_infty$ (we write $mathbb N_infty$ for the eventual value of the $mathbb N_k$), the integers $i$ and $j$ cannot be both in $mathbb N_infty$. Say that $i$ is not in $mathbb N_infty$. This means that $c(i)$ is in $text{Orb}(c(k))$ for some $kin K$, that is $kin g_2(mathbb N_n)$ for some $ninmathbb N$. Let $m$ be the minimum of $g_2(mathbb N_n)$. We get
                $$
                m<k
                $$

                (this is because we have $kne i$ in $(1)$, or, equivalently, $jge1$ in $(2)$) and $c(m)sim c(k)$ by definition of $sim$. As $c(i)intext{Orb}(c(k))$, we can write
                $$
                c(i)=c(k)+alpha
                $$

                with $alphainmathbb N^2$. Define $i'inmathbb N$ by
                $$
                c(i')=c(m)+alpha.
                $$

                It is easy to see, using the definition of Cantor's pairing function, that the last three displays imply $i'<i$.



                We get $c(i')sim c(i)notsim c(j)$, so that we can replace $(i,j)$ with $(i',j)$, which yields the contradiction $i'+j<i+j$ (recall that $i+j$ was assumed to be minimum).



                This shows that there are no $i,jinmathbb N$ such that $c(i)notsim c(j)$ but $f(c(i))=f(c(j))$, and thus that $f(alpha)=f(beta)iffalphasimbeta$. Therefore $sim$ is an arbitrary congruence, and we proved that it is finitely generated. $square$






                share|cite|improve this answer


























                  0












                  0








                  0






                  Edit. In fact every congruence on $mathbb N^n$ is finitely generated. In the book Finitely Generated Commutative Monoids by J. C. Rosales and P. A. García-Sánchez this is stated as Theorem 5.12 page 52, and is called "Rédei's Theorem". This result is sometimes formulated as "Finitely generated commutative monoids are finitely presented". It implies in particular that there are only countably many isomorphism classes of such monoids.



                  See also this MathOverflow question by John Baez.



                  End of Edit.





                  In his answer Lee Mosher asked the question:



                  Is the set of all isomorphism classes of $mathbb N^2$ orbits countable?



                  I must confess that I hadn't thought of this crucial question. The argument below shows that the answer is Yes.



                  Say that an equivalence relation $sim$ on $mathbb N^2$ is a congruence if
                  $$
                  alphasimbetaimplies alpha+gammasimbeta+gamma.
                  $$

                  for all $alpha,beta,gammainmathbb N^2$. There is an obvious notion of congruence generated by a relation on $mathbb N^2$.



                  If $sim$ is a congruence, $(mathbb N^2/sim,[(0,0)])$ is an $mathbb N^2$-orbit.



                  Conversely, if $(X,x_0)$ is an $mathbb N^2$-orbit, and if $f:mathbb N^2to X$ is the unique morphism of $mathbb N^2$-orbits from $(mathbb N^2,(0,0))$ to $(X,x_0)$, then the relation "$f(alpha )=f(beta)$" is a congruence on $mathbb N^2$, and $f$ induces an isomorphism
                  $$
                  (mathbb N^2/sim,[(0,0)])simeq(X,x_0).
                  $$

                  The idea behind the following lines is that, if $f(alpha)=f(beta)$, then the behavior of $f$ on the orbit of $beta$ is "the same" as its behavior on the orbit of $alpha$, so that, to know $f$ it suffices to know how it behaves on a single orbit by nonempty fiber.



                  Write $text{Orb}(x)$ for the orbit of $x$.



                  Lemma. If $alpha_0,alpha_1,dots$ is a sequence of points of $mathbb N^2$, then the ascending chain
                  $$
                  U_j:=bigcup_{i=0}^jtext{Orb}(alpha_i)
                  $$

                  stabilizes.



                  Proof. Let $m_1$ be the minimum (over $i$) of the $alpha_{i1}$ (with the notation $alpha_i=(alpha_{i1},alpha_{i2})$), define $m_2$ similarly, let $k$ and $ell$ be such that $alpha_{k1}=m_1$ and $alpha_{ell2}=m_2$. Then for $j$ larger than $k$ and $ell$ we have
                  $$
                  text{Orb}(alpha_k)cuptext{Orb}(alpha_ell)subset U_jsubsettext{Orb}(m_1,m_2).
                  $$

                  (Here and in the sequel $subset$ means "subset" - not necessarily proper.) As there are only finitely many subsets of $mathbb N^2$ which satisfy the two above inclusions, we are done. $square$



                  Claim. Any congruence on $mathbb N^2$ is finitely generated.



                  This will answer (in a positive way) Lee Mosher's question.



                  Proof. Let $(X,x_0)$ be an $mathbb N^2$-orbit, let $f:mathbb N^2to X$ be the morphism defined above, and let $c:mathbb Ntomathbb N^2$ be the inverse of Cantor's pairing function, so that we have
                  $$
                  mathbb Nxrightarrow cmathbb N^2xrightarrow fX.
                  $$

                  We will firstly specify a finite subset $G$ of $(mathbb N^2)^2$ such that $f(alpha)=f(beta)$ for all $(alpha,beta)in G$, and secondly we will define the congruence $sim$ on $mathbb N^2$ as the least congruence such that $alphasim beta$ for all $(alpha,beta)in G$. We'll obviously have $alphasimbetaimplies f(alpha)=f(beta)$, and we'll try to prove the converse implication.



                  If $S$ is a subset of $mathbb N$ and if $s:Ito S$ be the only map such that $I$ is an initial segment of $mathbb N$, and $s$ is increasing and surjective, we call $s$ the parametrization of $S$.



                  Let $P(mathbb N)$ be the set of subsets of $mathbb N$. We define a map
                  $$
                  g:P(mathbb N)to(P(mathbb N))^2,quad Smapsto(g_1(S),g_2(S))
                  $$

                  as follows:



                  Let $s:Ito S$ be the parametrization of $S$, so that we have
                  $$
                  Ixrightarrow sSxrightarrow cmathbb N^2xrightarrow fX; I,Ssubsetmathbb N.
                  $$



                  If $fcirc ccirc s$ is injective we set $g(S):=(S,varnothing)$.



                  Assume $fcirc ccirc s$ is not injective.



                  Write $F_isubset I$ for the fiber of $fcirc ccirc s$ containing $iin I$. Let $iin I$ be such that $F_i$ has at least two elements and $i$ is minimum for this condition. Set
                  $$
                  U:=bigcup_{kin F_isetminus{i}}text{Orb}(c(s(k))).qquad(1)
                  $$

                  Let $t:Jto F_isubset I$ be the parametrization of $F_i$, so that we have
                  $$
                  Jxrightarrow tF_ixrightarrow sSxrightarrow cmathbb N^2xrightarrow fX, Jsubsetmathbb N, F_isubset Isubsetmathbb N, Ssubsetmathbb N,
                  $$

                  and the lemma implies
                  $$
                  U=bigcup_{j=1}^mtext{Orb}(c(s(t(j))))qquad(2)
                  $$

                  for some $min Jsubsetmathbb N$. Then we set
                  $$
                  g_1(S):=c^{-1}(c(S)setminus U),
                  $$

                  $$
                  g_2(S):={s(t(1)),dots,s(t(m))}.
                  $$

                  Then ends the definition of
                  $$
                  g:P(mathbb N)to(P(mathbb N))^2,quad Smapsto(g_1(S),g_2(S)).
                  $$

                  Now we define the subsets
                  $$
                  mathbb N_0supsetmathbb N_1supsetmathbb N_2supsetcdots
                  $$

                  inductively by $mathbb N_0:=mathbb N$ and $mathbb N_i:=g_1(mathbb N_{i-1})$ for $ige1$.



                  As we remove from $mathbb N^2$ at least one orbit at each stage, the descending chain stabilizes by the lemma, and the union of the $g_2(mathbb N_i)$ is a finite set $K$:
                  $$
                  K:=bigcup_{iinmathbb N}g_2(mathbb N_i).
                  $$

                  We define the finite subset
                  $$
                  Gsubset(mathbb N^2)^2
                  $$

                  by decreeing that the couple $(alpha,beta)in(mathbb N^2)^2$ is in $G$ if and only if
                  $$
                  c^{-1}(alpha),c^{-1}(beta)in g_2(mathbb N_i)
                  $$

                  for some $iinmathbb N$.



                  As indicated above, we define the congruence $sim$ on $mathbb N^2$ as the least congruence such that $alphasimbeta$ for all $(alpha,beta)in G$. We obviously have $alphasimbetaimplies f(alpha)=f(beta)$.



                  Let us prove $f(alpha)=f(beta)impliesalphasimbeta$.



                  We assume by contradiction that there are $i,jinmathbb N$ such that $c(i)notsim c(j)$ but $f(c(i))=f(c(j))$. We also assume that $i+j$ is minimum for this condition.



                  As $fcirc c$ is injective on $mathbb N_infty$ (we write $mathbb N_infty$ for the eventual value of the $mathbb N_k$), the integers $i$ and $j$ cannot be both in $mathbb N_infty$. Say that $i$ is not in $mathbb N_infty$. This means that $c(i)$ is in $text{Orb}(c(k))$ for some $kin K$, that is $kin g_2(mathbb N_n)$ for some $ninmathbb N$. Let $m$ be the minimum of $g_2(mathbb N_n)$. We get
                  $$
                  m<k
                  $$

                  (this is because we have $kne i$ in $(1)$, or, equivalently, $jge1$ in $(2)$) and $c(m)sim c(k)$ by definition of $sim$. As $c(i)intext{Orb}(c(k))$, we can write
                  $$
                  c(i)=c(k)+alpha
                  $$

                  with $alphainmathbb N^2$. Define $i'inmathbb N$ by
                  $$
                  c(i')=c(m)+alpha.
                  $$

                  It is easy to see, using the definition of Cantor's pairing function, that the last three displays imply $i'<i$.



                  We get $c(i')sim c(i)notsim c(j)$, so that we can replace $(i,j)$ with $(i',j)$, which yields the contradiction $i'+j<i+j$ (recall that $i+j$ was assumed to be minimum).



                  This shows that there are no $i,jinmathbb N$ such that $c(i)notsim c(j)$ but $f(c(i))=f(c(j))$, and thus that $f(alpha)=f(beta)iffalphasimbeta$. Therefore $sim$ is an arbitrary congruence, and we proved that it is finitely generated. $square$






                  share|cite|improve this answer














                  Edit. In fact every congruence on $mathbb N^n$ is finitely generated. In the book Finitely Generated Commutative Monoids by J. C. Rosales and P. A. García-Sánchez this is stated as Theorem 5.12 page 52, and is called "Rédei's Theorem". This result is sometimes formulated as "Finitely generated commutative monoids are finitely presented". It implies in particular that there are only countably many isomorphism classes of such monoids.



                  See also this MathOverflow question by John Baez.



                  End of Edit.





                  In his answer Lee Mosher asked the question:



                  Is the set of all isomorphism classes of $mathbb N^2$ orbits countable?



                  I must confess that I hadn't thought of this crucial question. The argument below shows that the answer is Yes.



                  Say that an equivalence relation $sim$ on $mathbb N^2$ is a congruence if
                  $$
                  alphasimbetaimplies alpha+gammasimbeta+gamma.
                  $$

                  for all $alpha,beta,gammainmathbb N^2$. There is an obvious notion of congruence generated by a relation on $mathbb N^2$.



                  If $sim$ is a congruence, $(mathbb N^2/sim,[(0,0)])$ is an $mathbb N^2$-orbit.



                  Conversely, if $(X,x_0)$ is an $mathbb N^2$-orbit, and if $f:mathbb N^2to X$ is the unique morphism of $mathbb N^2$-orbits from $(mathbb N^2,(0,0))$ to $(X,x_0)$, then the relation "$f(alpha )=f(beta)$" is a congruence on $mathbb N^2$, and $f$ induces an isomorphism
                  $$
                  (mathbb N^2/sim,[(0,0)])simeq(X,x_0).
                  $$

                  The idea behind the following lines is that, if $f(alpha)=f(beta)$, then the behavior of $f$ on the orbit of $beta$ is "the same" as its behavior on the orbit of $alpha$, so that, to know $f$ it suffices to know how it behaves on a single orbit by nonempty fiber.



                  Write $text{Orb}(x)$ for the orbit of $x$.



                  Lemma. If $alpha_0,alpha_1,dots$ is a sequence of points of $mathbb N^2$, then the ascending chain
                  $$
                  U_j:=bigcup_{i=0}^jtext{Orb}(alpha_i)
                  $$

                  stabilizes.



                  Proof. Let $m_1$ be the minimum (over $i$) of the $alpha_{i1}$ (with the notation $alpha_i=(alpha_{i1},alpha_{i2})$), define $m_2$ similarly, let $k$ and $ell$ be such that $alpha_{k1}=m_1$ and $alpha_{ell2}=m_2$. Then for $j$ larger than $k$ and $ell$ we have
                  $$
                  text{Orb}(alpha_k)cuptext{Orb}(alpha_ell)subset U_jsubsettext{Orb}(m_1,m_2).
                  $$

                  (Here and in the sequel $subset$ means "subset" - not necessarily proper.) As there are only finitely many subsets of $mathbb N^2$ which satisfy the two above inclusions, we are done. $square$



                  Claim. Any congruence on $mathbb N^2$ is finitely generated.



                  This will answer (in a positive way) Lee Mosher's question.



                  Proof. Let $(X,x_0)$ be an $mathbb N^2$-orbit, let $f:mathbb N^2to X$ be the morphism defined above, and let $c:mathbb Ntomathbb N^2$ be the inverse of Cantor's pairing function, so that we have
                  $$
                  mathbb Nxrightarrow cmathbb N^2xrightarrow fX.
                  $$

                  We will firstly specify a finite subset $G$ of $(mathbb N^2)^2$ such that $f(alpha)=f(beta)$ for all $(alpha,beta)in G$, and secondly we will define the congruence $sim$ on $mathbb N^2$ as the least congruence such that $alphasim beta$ for all $(alpha,beta)in G$. We'll obviously have $alphasimbetaimplies f(alpha)=f(beta)$, and we'll try to prove the converse implication.



                  If $S$ is a subset of $mathbb N$ and if $s:Ito S$ be the only map such that $I$ is an initial segment of $mathbb N$, and $s$ is increasing and surjective, we call $s$ the parametrization of $S$.



                  Let $P(mathbb N)$ be the set of subsets of $mathbb N$. We define a map
                  $$
                  g:P(mathbb N)to(P(mathbb N))^2,quad Smapsto(g_1(S),g_2(S))
                  $$

                  as follows:



                  Let $s:Ito S$ be the parametrization of $S$, so that we have
                  $$
                  Ixrightarrow sSxrightarrow cmathbb N^2xrightarrow fX; I,Ssubsetmathbb N.
                  $$



                  If $fcirc ccirc s$ is injective we set $g(S):=(S,varnothing)$.



                  Assume $fcirc ccirc s$ is not injective.



                  Write $F_isubset I$ for the fiber of $fcirc ccirc s$ containing $iin I$. Let $iin I$ be such that $F_i$ has at least two elements and $i$ is minimum for this condition. Set
                  $$
                  U:=bigcup_{kin F_isetminus{i}}text{Orb}(c(s(k))).qquad(1)
                  $$

                  Let $t:Jto F_isubset I$ be the parametrization of $F_i$, so that we have
                  $$
                  Jxrightarrow tF_ixrightarrow sSxrightarrow cmathbb N^2xrightarrow fX, Jsubsetmathbb N, F_isubset Isubsetmathbb N, Ssubsetmathbb N,
                  $$

                  and the lemma implies
                  $$
                  U=bigcup_{j=1}^mtext{Orb}(c(s(t(j))))qquad(2)
                  $$

                  for some $min Jsubsetmathbb N$. Then we set
                  $$
                  g_1(S):=c^{-1}(c(S)setminus U),
                  $$

                  $$
                  g_2(S):={s(t(1)),dots,s(t(m))}.
                  $$

                  Then ends the definition of
                  $$
                  g:P(mathbb N)to(P(mathbb N))^2,quad Smapsto(g_1(S),g_2(S)).
                  $$

                  Now we define the subsets
                  $$
                  mathbb N_0supsetmathbb N_1supsetmathbb N_2supsetcdots
                  $$

                  inductively by $mathbb N_0:=mathbb N$ and $mathbb N_i:=g_1(mathbb N_{i-1})$ for $ige1$.



                  As we remove from $mathbb N^2$ at least one orbit at each stage, the descending chain stabilizes by the lemma, and the union of the $g_2(mathbb N_i)$ is a finite set $K$:
                  $$
                  K:=bigcup_{iinmathbb N}g_2(mathbb N_i).
                  $$

                  We define the finite subset
                  $$
                  Gsubset(mathbb N^2)^2
                  $$

                  by decreeing that the couple $(alpha,beta)in(mathbb N^2)^2$ is in $G$ if and only if
                  $$
                  c^{-1}(alpha),c^{-1}(beta)in g_2(mathbb N_i)
                  $$

                  for some $iinmathbb N$.



                  As indicated above, we define the congruence $sim$ on $mathbb N^2$ as the least congruence such that $alphasimbeta$ for all $(alpha,beta)in G$. We obviously have $alphasimbetaimplies f(alpha)=f(beta)$.



                  Let us prove $f(alpha)=f(beta)impliesalphasimbeta$.



                  We assume by contradiction that there are $i,jinmathbb N$ such that $c(i)notsim c(j)$ but $f(c(i))=f(c(j))$. We also assume that $i+j$ is minimum for this condition.



                  As $fcirc c$ is injective on $mathbb N_infty$ (we write $mathbb N_infty$ for the eventual value of the $mathbb N_k$), the integers $i$ and $j$ cannot be both in $mathbb N_infty$. Say that $i$ is not in $mathbb N_infty$. This means that $c(i)$ is in $text{Orb}(c(k))$ for some $kin K$, that is $kin g_2(mathbb N_n)$ for some $ninmathbb N$. Let $m$ be the minimum of $g_2(mathbb N_n)$. We get
                  $$
                  m<k
                  $$

                  (this is because we have $kne i$ in $(1)$, or, equivalently, $jge1$ in $(2)$) and $c(m)sim c(k)$ by definition of $sim$. As $c(i)intext{Orb}(c(k))$, we can write
                  $$
                  c(i)=c(k)+alpha
                  $$

                  with $alphainmathbb N^2$. Define $i'inmathbb N$ by
                  $$
                  c(i')=c(m)+alpha.
                  $$

                  It is easy to see, using the definition of Cantor's pairing function, that the last three displays imply $i'<i$.



                  We get $c(i')sim c(i)notsim c(j)$, so that we can replace $(i,j)$ with $(i',j)$, which yields the contradiction $i'+j<i+j$ (recall that $i+j$ was assumed to be minimum).



                  This shows that there are no $i,jinmathbb N$ such that $c(i)notsim c(j)$ but $f(c(i))=f(c(j))$, and thus that $f(alpha)=f(beta)iffalphasimbeta$. Therefore $sim$ is an arbitrary congruence, and we proved that it is finitely generated. $square$







                  share|cite|improve this answer














                  share|cite|improve this answer



                  share|cite|improve this answer








                  edited yesterday

























                  answered Jan 2 at 20:46









                  Pierre-Yves GaillardPierre-Yves Gaillard

                  13.2k23181




                  13.2k23181






























                      draft saved

                      draft discarded




















































                      Thanks for contributing an answer to Mathematics Stack Exchange!


                      • Please be sure to answer the question. Provide details and share your research!

                      But avoid



                      • Asking for help, clarification, or responding to other answers.

                      • Making statements based on opinion; back them up with references or personal experience.


                      Use MathJax to format equations. MathJax reference.


                      To learn more, see our tips on writing great answers.





                      Some of your past answers have not been well-received, and you're in danger of being blocked from answering.


                      Please pay close attention to the following guidance:


                      • Please be sure to answer the question. Provide details and share your research!

                      But avoid



                      • Asking for help, clarification, or responding to other answers.

                      • Making statements based on opinion; back them up with references or personal experience.


                      To learn more, see our tips on writing great answers.




                      draft saved


                      draft discarded














                      StackExchange.ready(
                      function () {
                      StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f3057838%2fhow-to-classify-mathbb-n2-orbits%23new-answer', 'question_page');
                      }
                      );

                      Post as a guest















                      Required, but never shown





















































                      Required, but never shown














                      Required, but never shown












                      Required, but never shown







                      Required, but never shown

































                      Required, but never shown














                      Required, but never shown












                      Required, but never shown







                      Required, but never shown







                      Popular posts from this blog

                      Mario Kart Wii

                      What does “Dominus providebit” mean?

                      Antonio Litta Visconti Arese